Parmenides | Page 3

Plato

including any form resulting from conversion by word pro- cessing or
hypertext software, but only so long as *EITHER*:
[*] The etext, when displayed, is clearly readable, and does *not*
contain characters other than those intended by the author of the work,
although tilde (~), asterisk (*) and underline (_) characters may be used
to convey punctuation intended by the author, and additional characters
may be used to indicate hypertext links; OR
[*] The etext may be readily converted by the reader at no expense into
plain ASCII, EBCDIC or equivalent form by the program that displays
the etext (as is the case, for instance, with most word processors); OR
[*] You provide, or agree to also provide on request at no additional
cost, fee or expense, a copy of the etext in its original plain ASCII form
(or in EBCDIC or other equivalent proprietary form).
[2] Honor the etext refund and replacement provisions of this "Small
Print!" statement.
[3] Pay a trademark license fee to the Project of 20% of the net profits
you derive calculated using the method you already use to calculate
your applicable taxes. If you don't derive profits, no royalty is due.
Royalties are payable to "Project Gutenberg
Association/Carnegie-Mellon University" within the 60 days following
each date you prepare (or were legally required to prepare) your annual
(or equivalent periodic) tax return.
WHAT IF YOU *WANT* TO SEND MONEY EVEN IF YOU
DON'T HAVE TO?
The Project gratefully accepts contributions in money, time, scanning
machines, OCR software, public domain etexts, royalty free copyright
licenses, and every other sort of contribution you can think of. Money
should be paid to "Project Gutenberg Association / Carnegie-Mellon

University".
*END*THE SMALL PRINT! FOR PUBLIC DOMAIN
ETEXTS*Ver.04.29.93*END*

This etext was prepared by Sue Asscher

PARMENIDES
by Plato

Translated by Benjamin Jowett

INTRODUCTION AND ANALYSIS.
The awe with which Plato regarded the character of 'the great'
Parmenides has extended to the dialogue which he calls by his name.
None of the writings of Plato have been more copiously illustrated,
both in ancient and modern times, and in none of them have the
interpreters been more at variance with one another. Nor is this
surprising. For the Parmenides is more fragmentary and isolated than
any other dialogue, and the design of the writer is not expressly stated.
The date is uncertain; the relation to the other writings of Plato is also
uncertain; the connexion between the two parts is at first sight
extremely obscure; and in the latter of the two we are left in doubt as to
whether Plato is speaking his own sentiments by the lips of Parmenides,
and overthrowing him out of his own mouth, or whether he is
propounding consequences which would have been admitted by Zeno
and Parmenides themselves. The contradictions which follow from the
hypotheses of the one and many have been regarded by some as
transcendental mysteries; by others as a mere illustration, taken at
random, of a new method. They seem to have been inspired by a sort of
dialectical frenzy, such as may be supposed to have prevailed in the
Megarian School (compare Cratylus, etc.). The criticism on his own
doctrine of Ideas has also been considered, not as a real criticism, but as
an exuberance of the metaphysical imagination which enabled Plato to
go beyond himself. To the latter part of the dialogue we may certainly
apply the words in which he himself describes the earlier philosophers

in the Sophist: 'They went on their way rather regardless of whether we
understood them or not.'
The Parmenides in point of style is one of the best of the Platonic
writings; the first portion of the dialogue is in no way defective in ease
and grace and dramatic interest; nor in the second part, where there was
no room for such qualities, is there any want of clearness or precision.
The latter half is an exquisite mosaic, of which the small pieces are
with the utmost fineness and regularity adapted to one another. Like the
Protagoras, Phaedo, and others, the whole is a narrated dialogue,
combining with the mere recital of the words spoken, the observations
of the reciter on the effect produced by them. Thus we are informed by
him that Zeno and Parmenides were not altogether pleased at the
request of Socrates that they would examine into the nature of the one
and many in the sphere of Ideas, although they received his suggestion
with approving smiles. And we are glad to be told that Parmenides was
'aged but well-favoured,' and that Zeno was 'very good-looking'; also
that Parmenides affected to decline the great argument, on which, as
Zeno knew from experience, he was not unwilling to enter. The
character of Antiphon, the half-brother of Plato, who had once
Continue reading on your phone by scaning this QR Code

 / 48
Tip: The current page has been bookmarked automatically. If you wish to continue reading later, just open the Dertz Homepage, and click on the 'continue reading' link at the bottom of the page.